The Man Who Wasn’t There: Tales
from the Edge of the Self. By Anil Ananthaswamy. Dutton. $16.
Readers interested in a
blending of scientific research with philosophical speculation and forays into
artistic endeavors will be fascinated by Anil Ananthaswamy’s The Man Who Wasn’t There, originally
published last year and now available in paperback. The front cover gives the
subtitle as “Tales from the Edge of the Self,” but the title page is more
informative, giving it as “Investigations into the Strange New Science of the
Self.” In fact, although there are tales, and parts of tales, in the book, it
is the science underlying the anecdotes and stories that primarily interests
Ananthaswamy, a consultant to New
Scientist, where he was formerly a deputy news editor. Unlike a book that
it appears on the surface to resemble, neurologist Oliver Sacks’ 1985 The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat,
Ananthaswamy’s work does not dwell on the personal elements of the stories the
author tells, using them instead to set up scientific discussions. Thus, the reports
about people with schizophrenia, autism, body image integrity disorder (BIID),
and other conditions are less the focus than the conditions themselves – the
result being a comparatively clinical and at times dry look at the brain and the way
its functions are reflected in everything from mental illness to modern art,
rather than a series of human-interest stories told from a foundational
scientific perspective.
The way a reader approaches
Ananthaswamy’s book will thus determine a great deal of what he or she gets out
of it. Those interested in the neurological and
biological bases of conditions such as autism, ecstatic epilepsy, even
Alzheimer’s disease, will absorb more from The
Man Who Wasn’t There than those looking for stories about the impact of
these conditions of the everyday lives of the people who have them – and on those
around them. Ananthaswamy’s narrative is
more textbookish than empathetic. For instance, rather than discussing the
tremendous impact of Alzheimer’s disease on caregivers as well as patients,
Ananthaswamy prefers to look at what Alzheimer’s indicates about whatever the
notion of “self” may be. Referring to a scientist at the Toronto Rehabilitation
Institute, he writes, “Pia Kontos is not comfortable with claims that
Alzheimer’s disease patients ultimately have no self. She argues that even in
the face of severe cognitive decline evident in Alzheimer’s patients a form of
selfhood persists, a precognitive, prereflective selfhood that’s embedded in
the body.” In a similar vein, rather than provide a seamless narrative about a
schizophrenic man who eventually committed suicide, Ananthaswamy pauses midway through
the story for a paragraph of history: “Schizophrenia was originally called
dementia praecox, a term coined in the 1890s by the German psychiatrist Emil
Kraepelin. It was Swiss psychiatrist Eugen Bleuler who renamed it schizophrenia
in 1908. …Yet another stereotype, popularized by the antipsychiatry movement
and some of the literary avant-garde, was of the schizophrenic as a
romanticized wild man, in touch with his deepest desires and instincts.”
It is difficult to get a
handle on where Ananthaswamy is going with the various case histories and
scientific analyses he presents, at least until he ties things up in an
epilogue that is managed rather neatly. The case-by-case instances are more
problematic. For instance, the BIID chapter does not get into what form of
selfhood is involved in people wishing to conform externally to their internal
identity as amputees. People who have amputations out of necessity are often
greatly determined to use prostheses to reduce the chance of being perceived as
amputees and evaluated through that lens; but people with BIID wish to match
their external appearance to their internal self-image by having amputations
done unnecessarily. What this implies about the self, Ananthaswamy does not
explore. He has less interest in this sort of individual-person-centered query
than in more-general matters: “In adults, a set of brain regions is strongly
correlated with theory of mind: the temporoparietal junction (TPI), the
precuneus (PC), and the medial prefrontal cortex (MPFC). These brain regions
are activated when you think about what others are thinking. MIT’s Rebecca Saxe
studied these brain regions in children five to eleven years old, ages when
they are developing and honing their theory-of-mind abilities. Turns out the
same brain regions are implicated in these children in tasks that require
theory of mind. In fact, the right temporoparietal junction (rTPI) is most
strongly correlated with theory-of-mind abilities in children.”
This sort of objective,
analytical narrative pervades The Man Who
Wasn’t There, and readers who find this rather coolly removed style
conducive to thoughtful exploration of issues of self and identity will be
drawn to the book. So will readers who are interested in philosophical debates
that are couched in terms more dense and abstruse than they are transparent and
accessible: “One hard-nosed way of looking at the self is to ask whether it can
exist independent of all else – as a fundamental part of reality, giving it a
unique place in the basic categories, or ontology, of things that make up
reality – a self that could not be explained away as being constituted of
things with a more basic ontological status.” Readers who find this sort of
thinking and argument prolonged to the point of tedium are not the intended
audience here; neither are those hoping to learn much of real-world, everyday
applicability from Ananthaswamy’s case histories. This is a book for thinkers
with a penchant for scientific research into philosophical questions. For
others, it is neither particularly accessible nor, ultimately, particularly
revelatory.
No comments:
Post a Comment